Chapter Three Voluntary Informed Consent 1 Introduction The requirement to obtain voluntary informed consent from individuals before they are enrolled in a research trial is a fundamental principle of research ethics. This requirement is reflected in all published national and international codes, regulations, and guidelines pertaining to research ethics, including those in many developing countries, such as India, Thailand, and Uganda. It also appears in a major international human rights instrument—the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights—to which the United States is a party. Article 7 of this covenant provides that "no one shall be subjected without his free consent to medical or scientific experimentation" (United Nations 1996).The requirement for freely given and informed consent to participate in research reflects important substantive ethical principles, including respect for persons, human dignity, and autonomy. However, it is possible to respect persons and their dignity or autonomy and affirm the requirement to obtain voluntary informed consent and at the same time allow for the modification of the procedures that are involved in obtaining consent, such as those stipulated in the Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects, known as the Common Rule (45 CFR 46.117(c)).2 Despite the ethical centrality of voluntary informed consent and its underlying principles, problems of inter-pretation and application exist for researchers and ethics review committees in both developed and developing countries. Some problems regarding informed consent are particularly difficult when the host country has little experience with clinical trials and has markedly different cultural values and ethical commitments than the United States. It is important, therefore, for U.S. sponsors of international research to address pressing issues concerning the application of U.S. research regulations for informed consent in settings with different cultures and customs. This chapter addresses a number of related topics, including the following:
Although individual voluntary informed consent by competent adults is a widely accepted standard in most research environments, it is not universally embraced. Nonetheless, the National Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC) remains convinced that U.S. sponsors ofresearch in developing countries should adhere to internationally agreed-upon ethical standards of voluntary informed consent for research, even in the face of cultural diversity. Obtaining adequately informed voluntary consent from individual research participants is a necessary requirement in preventing exploitation, and it should be possible to remain sensitive to cultural differences without departing from these standards. The justification for the need for obtaining informed voluntary consent is simple: The use of human beings as a means to the ends of others without their knowledge and freely granted permission constitutes exploitation and is therefore unethical. NBAC recognizes, however, that disagreement still exists about this claim. One commentator has argued that "[i]t is `ethical imperialism' at its worst to assume that the informed consent requirement,which does indeed serve one (only one) moral principlein the Western setting, is in itself such a universal ethicalstandard" (Newton 1990, 11). This same commentator contends that growing doubt surrounds the values of individualism and individual rights, so "the investigator might better stick to the research, and accept the local assessment as to adequate protection of individual rights" (Newton 1990, 11). Two other commentators, Ijsselmuiden and Faden, take an opposing view: "Appeals to cultural sensitivity... are no substitute for careful moral analysis. We see no convincing arguments for a general policy of dispensing with, or substantially modifying, the researcher's obligation to obtain first-person consent in biomedical research conducted in Africa" (1992, 833). They add that defenders of such a policy "have relied on limited and often dated anthropologic literature that does not reflect the rapid cultural changes brought about by colonialism and independence, warfare, and urbanization" (1992, 833). The recommendations developed in this chapter focus on three traditional elements of informed consent (Faden and Beauchamp 1986): 1) disclosing information to potential research participants (see Exhibit 3.1); 2) ascertaining their understanding of what has been disclosed; and 3) ensuring that their agreement to participate in research is voluntary. The basic elements of disclosure in the informed consent process as presented in the Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects are listed in Exhibit 3.1. References in this chapter to the basic elements of disclosure in informed consent are to these eight requirements. The Ethical Standard of Informed ConsentVarious descriptions of the process and nature of informed consent can be found in the Common Rule (45 CFR 46.116 and 46.117), Food and Drug Administration (FDA) regulations (21 CFR 56), the Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS) International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects (CIOMS 1993), the International Conference on Harmonisation (ICH) ICH Harmonised Tripartite Guideline, Guideline for Good Clinical Practice (GCP) (ICH 1996), and the World Medical Association's (WMA) Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects (WMA 1964, as amended in 1996 and again in 2000). Principle 9 of the 1996 revision of the Declaration of Helsinki states that "[i]n any research on human beings, each potential subject must be adequately informed of the aims, methods, anticipated benefits and potential hazards of the study and the discomfort it may entail. He or she should be informed that he or she is at liberty to abstain from participation in the study and that he or she is free to withdraw his or her consent to participation at any time. The physician should then obtain the subject's freely given informed consent, preferably in writing" (WMA 1964, as amended in 1996). In the October 2000 revised Declaration of Helsinki, Principle 22 addresses the informed consent process, stating that: [I]n any research on human beings, each potential subject must be adequately informed of the aims, methods, sources of funding, any possible conflicts of interest, institutional affiliations of the researcher, the anticipated benefits and potential risks of the study and the discomfort it may entail. The subject should be informed of the right to abstain from participation in the study or to withdraw consent to participate at any time without reprisal. After ensuring that the subject has understood the information, the physician National Bioethics Advisory Commission should then obtain the subject's freely given informed consent, preferably in writing. If the consent cannot be obtained in writing, the non-written consent must be formally documented and witnessed (WMA 1964, as amended in 2000).
Substantive changes between the 1996 and 2000 revisions of the Declaration include 1) informing each potential subject about any possible conflicts of interest and the institutional affiliations of the researcher; 2) ensuring that research participants have understood the information presented to them; and 3) requiring that if the consent cannot be obtained in writing, the nonwritten consent must be formally documented and witnessed. For this report, NBAC adopts, as the clearest and most appropriate guides for discussion, the following definitions of informed consent and the substantive standard of informed consent: Informed consent is a process by which an individual voluntarily expresses his or her willingness to participate in a particular trial, after having been informed of all aspects of the trial that are relevant to the decision to participate. This definition is adopted from the ICH Guideline for Good Clinical Practice, GCP Guideline 1.28 (ICH 1996). An important feature of this definition is that it focuses on the process of obtaining consent rather than on the documentation of that process using, for example, a written, signed, and dated form. In an ethically sound consent process, a member of the research team provides information to the potential participant, determines that the individual understands the information provided, and ensures that the individual voluntarily agrees to participate. Although consent traditionally has been documented by the signing of a consent form, other methods of documentation often are acceptable or even preferable, such as oral consent with a witness signature. In many settings, it is also required that the person obtaining the consent sign the consent form or other related documents and that a witness (or person designated by the participant) attests to the process. It is always essential to make a distinction between the consent document and the consent process and to not allow the document itself to constitute the process. The phrase substantive standard of informed consent refers to the requirement to obtain voluntary informed consent and reflects the principle that competent individuals are entitled to choose freely whether to participate in research. This definition was adopted from the CIOMS International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects, Guideline 1, Commentary, para. 2 (CIOMS 1993, 13). In general, voluntary informed consent protects the individual's freedom of choice, respects his or her personhood, dignity, and autonomy, and reduces the chances of exploitation. Objections to this substantive ethical standard are rarely, if ever, voiced, even in parts of the world in which less cultural emphasis is placed on individual rights and freedom of choice than is common in Western and most developed countries. However, various objections often arise about the need for certain procedures for obtaining and documenting informed consent, including those stipulated in U.S. research regulations and other documents, such as the ICH Guideline for Good Clinical Practice. As noted, it is important to distinguish substantive ethical principles and standards from the procedures that implement them. Although procedures are important, they often can be modified without compromising ethical principles or standards. Examples of procedural aspects of the informed consent process and its documentation include the following requirements: the informed consent documents should be in writing and signed by the research participant; the consent form should be signed by the person obtaining consent or by the principal investigator; and there should be a witness to the signing of consent forms. Other examples of procedures that are not always central to meeting the substantive ethical principles and standards of voluntary informed consent are involving family members in the consent process or obtaining a community leader's permission before approaching individuals in the community. Although it is necessary—and not always easy—to determine which procedural aspects are ethically required and which might be altered or waived altogether, procedural requirements should be viewed as less fundamental than matters of substantive ethical standards or principles. Recommendation 3.1: Research should not deviate from the substantive ethical standard of voluntary informed consent. Researchers should not propose, sponsors should not support, and ethics review committees should not approve research that deviates from this substantive ethical standard. Cultural Barriers Relating to Disclosure Requirements Requirements for disclosing information in research settings usually exceed those for disclosing information in clinical contexts. In the United States, the requirements for disclosure of information to potential participants in research are specific and detailed. (See Exhibit 3.1.) The extent of medical information that is disclosed to patients in clinical settings differs among cultures and can influence judgments about the amount and kind of information that should be disclosed in research settings. Three principal types of disclosure are central to the process of informed consent in the research setting: 1) disclosure of diagnosis and risk; 2) disclosure of the use of placebos and randomization; and 3) disclosure of alternative treatments. In addition, NBAC considers a fourth type of disclosure—that of the possibility of access to any post-trial benefits—a central issue discussed in Chapter 4. Disclosure of Diagnosis and Risk In some parts of the world, it is still customary for physicians to withhold certain information from patients.3 Clinicians often provide diagnoses (as well as prognoses) of cancer or other serious conditions to family members, but they withhold such information from patients. As a result, the patient's consent to certain procedures, if sought, may not be fully informed. Jeremy Sugarman and his colleagues noted in their report to NBAC that "[i]n one country, complete information about medical diagnoses and prognoses are withheld routinely from patients with certain diseases, such as cancer. Consequently, valid informed consent (for either treatment or research participation) can be difficult or impossible."4 Nancy Kass and Adnan Hyder describe a similar situation in their study for NBAC: "...in some developing country settings, a diagnosis of cancer would never be revealed directly to the patient but rather to members of the patient's family."5 Although this observation was made in reference to clinical care, these cultural practices are relevant to research participants, who may have similar expectations. Similarly, different cultures have different attitudes toward the disclosure of risks in the clinical context, and some researchers believe that it is not always appropriate to disclose to patients the full ramifications of their situation. In another study conducted for NBAC, Nigerian researchers indicated that consent documents attached to certain research protocols included information that potential participants might find extraneous, irrelevant, or culturally inappropriate. These researchers called particular attention to the emphasis placed on explaining the potential risks to study participants, noting that in the United States, there is much greater interest in communicating the possibility of harm to research participants than there is in Nigeria. One physician noted that, given Nigerian cultural norms, disclosing all possible risks would unnecessarily alarm potential research participants associated with the research.6 Based on such observations, some people believe that, at least in some cultures, it would be impossible to enroll research participants by adhering to the basic elements of disclosure as presented in 45 CFR 46.116(a). NBAC believes that cultural standards regarding the inappropriateness of providing diagnoses and prognoses to patients or research participants do not justify deviation from the substantive ethical standard of informed consent in research. Even if the custom of routinely withholding complete information about diagnoses and prognoses from patients with certain diseases could be defended in ordinary medical practice, it poses a severe challenge to the need to adhere to the substantive ethical standard of disclosure required for research involving human participants. Those who lack information about their diagnosis and prognosis cannot be expected to understand the purpose of the research, any potential direct benefits, the risks of not participating, or the alternatives to participation. Similarly, potential participants cannot make an informed decision to participate without knowing that they may not receive a proven treatment that could be beneficial. Enrolling individuals in research who are not given the opportunity to understand such important information represents a deviation from the substantive ethical standard of disclosure required for adequate informed consent and should not be permitted. Diversity in the practice of disclosing information in the clinical context does not alter the requirements for such disclosure in the research context. These matters must be studied in more detail to learn about how cultural variations affect the meaning and effectiveness of the consent process and the use of particular consent documents. It is critical that we find innovative and culturally responsive ways to disclose information to potential participants. NBAC heard testimony from U.S. and developing country researchers who have succeeded in adhering to this standard,7 even though doing so often takes more time and effort than researchers typically expend in the informed consent process. Even in cultures in which a diagnosis of serious illness is not normally revealed in the treatment context, researchers often can find ways to overcome this barrier to disclosure in the research setting. Disclosure About Control Interventions and RandomizationIn some cultural contexts, questions also arise regarding the appropriateness of requiring information to be disclosed about the use of a placebo in one arm of a clinical trial, the randomization of participants, and any uncertainty that may exist regarding the efficacy of an experimental intervention. Sugarman and his colleagues reported on "local perceptions concerning cultural barriers to randomization and the use of placebos." Indeed, investigators sometimes struggled with these barriers, responding in different ways. For example, in one case, investigators who believed that it would be impossible to obtain valid informed consent for a randomized trial abandoned the use of randomization in their research. However, in another case, investigators used placebos, even though they did not believe that the research participants understood the implications of doing so.8 Despite these barriers, cultural differences do not provide adequate justification for foregoing the requirement to disclose key elements of the nature of the clinical trial, such as the use of a placebo or the randomization of participants into different trial arms. Disclosure of Alternative Therapies An example from the literature illustrates a particular disclosure problem. Love and Fost (1997) describe a struggle that occurred in one U.S. IRB that reviewed a proposal for a randomized clinical trial of adjuvant treatment for breast cancer to be conducted in Vietnam. The investigator "found himself uncertain about the application of American standards of informed consent in the Vietnamese setting." After consultation with experts on Vietnam and Vietnamese culture, he concluded that "American standards would not be acceptable to Vietnamese physicians, political leaders in Vietnam, or the vast majority of Vietnamese patients" (Love and Fost 1997, 424). The investigator argued that in medical practice in Vietnam, patients do not participate in their medical decisions. Thus, the researcher contended that participants in the clinical trial should not receive any information that would convey the treating doctor's uncertainty—specifically, information about alternative therapies and the use of randomization to determine the subject's proposed treatment (Love and Fost 1997) Although the Commission recognizes the challenges raised by these cultural differences in practicing medicine and obtaining consent, it does not believe that these challenges provide adequate justification for foregoing the requirement to make disclosures about alternative therapies that are available to potential participants should they choose not to enter a clinical trial. Recommendation 3.2: Researchers should develop culturally appropriate ways to disclose information that is necessary for adherence to the substantive ethical standard of informed consent, with particular attention to disclosures relating todiagnosis and risk, research design, and possible post-trial benefits. Researchers should describe in their protocols and justify to the ethics review committee(s) the procedures they plan to use fordisclosing such information to participants. The basic disclosure requirements for satisfying the informed consent provisions in U.S. research regulations (see Exhibit 3.1) focus on information needed by a potential participant to decide whether or not to participate in a study. Of the eight basic disclosure requirements, one focuses on potential benefits: "a description of any benefits to the subject or to others which may reasonably be expected from the research" (45 CFR 46.116(a)(1)). Traditionally, such a disclosure has been required to ensure that potential participants understand whether there is any possibility that the intervention itself might benefit them while they are enrolled in the study. There is, however, no specific mention of any post-trial benefits.In any case, those who may participate in studies should be informed of the potential benefits, if any, that they might receive by doing so. Because this information is relevant to participants' decisions to participate in the research, ethics review committees should require investigators to make these disclosures. Recommendation 3.3: Ethics review committees should require that researchers include in theinformed consent process and consent documents information about what benefits, if any, will be available to research participants when their participation in the study in question has ended. In some cultures, the belief system of potential research participants does not explain health and disease using the concepts and terms of modern medical science and technology. This is significant, because when people do not understand or accept scientific explanations of health and disease, the challenge of obtaining informed consent can be daunting.9 Patricia Marshall's report to NBAC quotes one physician as follows: "...[W]hat I worry about is whether we are really informing them. We are talking to a society that does not believe in the germtheory of disease so it's difficult to explain." The researcher provided an example of the pervasive belief that a person's death is a result of sorcery rather than a lethal infection.10 In noting that he had encountered a cultural belief that spirits cause epilepsy, Alfred Sommer, Dean of the Johns Hopkins University School of Hygiene nd Public Health, told NBAC that "we do not want to fight a belief system. We simply say we have this pill. We believe it is safe. We think it may reduce the recurrence of the following thing. We would like you to take it."11 Despite this potential barrier to adequate understanding, if they are willing to devote the time and effort to do so, researchers often are able to devise creative measures for overcoming these barriers. An example appears in the Kass/Hyder report for NBAC: "...the concept of immunology, an immune response, that there's something in your blood that's going to attack bacteria and viruses which you also don't have a concept for....[H]ow much can someone really focus on the consent form when they have this whole new idea that there's this battle going on in their bloodstream?...When we go and translate, we try to use, for example, immune cells, we talk about people who guard houses...it's a particular kind of watchman. So you have a particular kind of watchman in your blood...."12 Even in countries with very low literacy rates (e.g., 30 percent for men and 10 percent for women in Senegal), one group found that "widespread illiteracy is not a barrier to comprehension, especially since informed consent is more an interactive process than one that depends on reading" (Preziosi et al. 1997, 372). However, the authors of this study concluded that understanding abstract scientific concepts, such as double blinding and randomization, could be difficult. To help explain these complex issues, researchers used terms and concepts that were understandable to the community involved: "To illustrate the principle of randomization and the possibility that one of the vaccines might fail, the presenters used a familiar agricultural example: the evaluation of fertilizers or of seed varieties on randomized plots, a procedure familiar to farmers in the area" (Preziosi et al. 1997, 370). Another illustration emphasizes the importance of educating individuals and the community about the study and its specific purpose and procedures. Investigators and research assistants interviewed by Marshall noted that education should begin at the community level. "You approach some person as a contact person...you often start with the local governance...we need to obtain permission from them and we need their help to get to community leaders...they need to work with community leaders...we spend time discussing [thestudy]...you have to explain [it] fully."13 Researchers may find, for example, that, in circumstances where they do not speak the local language, the use of intermediaries can be an effective means of ensuring adequate understanding among potential participants. In some countries, a process of community education acts as a precursor to the process of obtaining individual consent. For example, one study reported that in Senegal, the field staff and physicians held meetings in each village to provide information about a study of a new pertussis vaccine and to obtain consensus about its use. A physician then provided additional information and sought individual informed consent at the monthly vaccination session. A clinical trial for vaccination against Haemophilus influenzae type b in The Gambia was preceded by an intensive publicity campaign involving radio, newspapers, and discussions with village leaders (Leach et al. 1999). When mothers attended the first child health clinic, they received an information sheet about the clinical trial to take home for discussion with their families. When a mother returned for the first vaccination, the trial worker explained the study again, and, if the mother gave oral consent, the trial worker signed the information sheet. Translation and back translation of a written consent form may be one way of ensuring that information is correctly disclosed; however, this may not always be effective. Jean Pape, a researcher from Haiti, who is also on the Cornell University faculty, described the complexity of this process.14 In preparing to begin HIV vaccine trials in Haiti, his research group needed approval from its own IRB in Haiti, as well as from the IRB at Vanderbilt University—one of the collaborators—and from the IRB at Cornell University Medical School. To be understandable to participants, the consent form had to be in the Creole language. Yet, the document also had to be in French, the language of the Haitian researchers. Because the consent form had to be reviewed by the Cornell IRB, a translation in English was also required. Pape said that the back translation of a consent form "does not guarantee that volunteers have really understood the objective of the study, the risks and advantages, and their voluntary participation,"15 a difficulty reported in another study in Nigeria.16 NBAC also heard about the desirability of testing research participants to understand whether and how much they understood regarding the informed consent process.17 Pape described the process he regularly undertakes to ensure understanding. This process includes a person who counsels potential participants about all aspects of the project, helps to develop a test questionnaire that all potential participants must pass before being given the actual consent form, and is available to address participants' concerns and questions. The period before obtaining ethical clearance from the various review committees is used to counsel and inform potential volunteers, who should pass this test of understanding before receiving a simpler informed consent form.18 These mechanisms—the counseling sessions and test questionnaires—illustrate some of the ways in which informed consent can and should be a process that takes place over time and that is much more than the mere signing of a document that may be imperfectly comprehended. Despite the acknowledged difficulties of administering tests of understanding, NBAC supports the idea of incorporating these tests into research protocols. Recommendation 3.4: Researchers should develop procedures to ensure that potential participants do, in fact, understand the information provided in the consent process and should describe those Recommendation 3.5: Researchers should consult with community representatives to develop innovative and effective means to communicate all necessary information in a manner that is understandable to potential participants. When community representatives will not be involved, the protocol presented to the ethics review committee should justify why such involvement is not possible or relevant. In some cultures, investigators must obtain permission from a community leader or village council before approaching potential research participants. Yet, it is important to distinguish between obtaining permission to enter a community for the purpose of conducting research and for obtaining individual informed consent. In their reports, NBAC consultants all noted that the role of community leaders or elders is an integral part of the process of recruiting research participants. Although these reports typically use the terminology of consent to refer to the community's permission or a leader's authorization for the researchers to approach individuals, NBAC will use this term to refer to the permission or authorization given by the individual being recruited as a research participant. The need to obtain permission from a community leader before approaching individuals does not need to compromise the ethical standard requiring an individual's voluntary informed consent to participate in research. Gaining permission from a community leader is no different, in many circumstances, from the common requirement in this country of obtaining permission from a school principal before involving pupils in research, from a nursing home director before approaching individual residents, or from a workplace supervisor before initiating an experimental screening program. An ethical problem arises only when the community leader exerts pressure on the community in a way that compromises the voluntariness of individual consent. The reports commissioned by NBAC describe a number of situations in which community leaders have been involved in the informed consent process. (See Exhibit 3.2.) Nevertheless, recruitment procedures in some cultures involve community leaders whose authority does not allow individual members of the community to refuse to participate in research for which the leader has National Bioethics Advisory Commission granted permission. Also, in some settings, authoritarian governments may limit autonomous decisionmaking by their citizens, which may affect their participation inresearch.27 The question then arises regarding whether there are some countries in which U.S. researchers should not engage in international collaborative research. In NBAC's view, if a country's political system or a local situation makes it impossible for individuals' consent to be voluntary and that fact is known in advance, then, because U.S. researchers cannot adhere to the substantive ethical standard of informed consent, it would be inappropriate for them to choose such settings. Recommendation 3.6: Where culture or custom requires that permission of a community representative be granted before researchers may approach potential research participants, researchers should be sensitive to such local requirements. However, in no case may permission from a community representative or council replace the requirement of a competent individual's voluntary informed consent.
Recommendation 3.7: Researchers should strive to ensure that individuals agree to participate in research without coercion or undue inducements from community leaders or representatives It is customary although not required in some societies for other members of a potential research participant's family to be involved in the informed consent process. In most instances, the need to involve the family is not intended as a substitute for individual consent, but rather as an additional step in the process.28 An example of a multistep process involving the family is described by Loue and colleagues (Loue and Okello 2000) in their report on a workshop in Uganda that addressed the problem of acquiescence by another family member in order for an individual to participate in research. (See Exhibit 3.3.) Researchers in other countries also have reported on their efforts to involve the family in the informed consent process in ways that do not undermine the standard of individual consent. Marshall reported, for example, that in Nigeria in areas where traditional cultural norms are strong, the permission of a woman's husband might be required before she can enroll in research. A Nigerian physician involved in a breast cancer study noted that cancer patients often need the approval of their husbands to participate in research. However, the physician also emphasized that in such cases, the woman's individual consent is still essential. Indeed, most investigators have developed strategies that accommodate and encourage discussion regarding study participation with family members.29 NBAC recognizes that this situation does not apply in cases in which a family member lacks the capacity to give informed consent. Indeed, there is consensus that having the capacity to decide is an important precondition (or threshold element) for informed consent (Beauchamp and Childress 1994; NBAC 1998). In many cases, family members may be approached before asking an individual directly to participate in a research project. However, seeking permission from family members without engaging the potential research participants at all clearly departs from the ethical standard of informed consent. On the other hand, potential participants might also choose to involve others, such as family members, in the consent process. Indeed, involving family or community members in the informed consent process need not diminish, and might even enhance, the individual's ability to make his or her choices and to give informed consent (or refusal).
These examples show that it is often possible to obtain individual informed consent, which may require and indeed benefit from the involvement of family or community members, while at the same time preserving cultural norms. Such involvement ranges from providing written information sheets for potential participants to take home and discuss with family members to holding community meetings during which information is presented about the research and community consensus is obtained. When the potential participant wishes to involve family members in the consent discussion, the researcher should take appropriate steps to accommodate this desire. Recommendation 3.8: When a potential research participant wishes to involve family members in the consent process, the researcher should take appropriate steps to accommodate this wish. In nocase, however, may a family member's permission replace the requirement of a competent individual's voluntary informed consent. Some cultures customarily require the permission of a woman's husband, if she is married, or her father, if she is unmarried, before she can enroll in a research protocol. A strict requirement that a husband must first grant per- mission before researchers may enroll his wife in research treats the woman as subordinate to her husband and as less than fully autonomous. If the requirement of spousal authorization, in addition to individual informed consent, were applied equally to enrollment of men and women as research participants, it would at least constitute gender equity. But in cultures in which spousal authorization for participation in research is customary, it appears always to be the woman who must obtain her husband's permission. If women wish to consult with their husbands or to seek voluntarily to obtain their husbands' permission before deciding to enroll in research, this is not only ethically permissible, but in some contexts highly desirable. However, a strict requirement of spousal authorization violates the substantive respect for persons principle, which mandates that equal respect be accorded to women as persons. Much research is directed at conditions that affect both women and men. Yet, it is important not to neglect research on diseases or conditions that affect only women. In reality, without involving the husband in the consent procedures, it may be impossible to conduct some research on common and serious health problems that affect only women. In such cases, a likely consequence would be a lack of knowledge on which to base health care decisions for women in that country. The prospect of denying such a substantial benefit to all women in a particular culture or country calls for a narrow exception to the requirement that researchers use the same procedures in the consent process for women as for men, one that would allow for obtaining the permission of a man in addition to the woman's consent. Recommendation 3.9: Researchers should use the same procedures in the informed consent process for women and men. However, ethics review committees may accept a consent process in which a woman's individual consent to participate in research is supplemented by permission from a man if all of the following conditions are met: a) it would be impossible to conduct the research without obtaining such supplemental permission; and b) failure to conduct this research could deny its potential benefits to women in the host country; and c) measures to respect the woman's autonomy to consent to research are undertaken to the greatest extent possible. In no case may a competent adult woman be enrolled in research solely upon the consent of another person; her individual consent is always required. It is likely to be difficult to decide when a study design constitutes an undue influence. One definition states that "undue influence...occurs through an offer of an excessive, unwarranted, inappropriate or improper reward or other overture in order to obtain compliance" (National Commission 1979, 14). There are many circumstances that can cause undue inducements to participate in clinical trials, including offers of medical care not otherwise available or offers of money. Discussions in the literature traditionally have focused on monetary payments to research participants and address the question of whether any amount of money is an acceptable inducement, and, if so, at what point the acceptable inducement becomes undue (Dickert and Grady 1999; Macklin 1981; Macklin 1982). Other aspects of research design that may pose a problem of undue influence have received considerably less attention. As the CIOMS Guidelines document acknowledges: "It may be difficult to distinguish between suitable recompense and undue influence to participate in research....Someone without access to medical care may be unduly influenced to participate in research simply to receive such care" (CIOMS 1993, 19). This situation is likely to exist in developing countries in which large numbers of people have little or no access to medical care and treatment even for ordinary illnesses, a concern expressed to NBAC in testimony.32 It is necessary, then, to answer the threshold question of whether the very offer to participate in research constitutes an undue inducement to citizens of developing countries who have little or no access to medical care and treatment (Bernstein 1999). Even a placebo-controlled trial offers such individuals a 50 percent likelihood (in a two-arm trial) of receiving an intervention that, although unproven, may be beneficial. If the solution to this fundamental problem is to forgo research entirely in such places, it might make those populations worse off than they would be if research goes forward. This consideration requires the review of the ethical consequences of not conducting research and the determination of whether those consequences outweigh the ethical problems alleged to exist in the conduct of the research. But the need to attempt such a balance can be avoided if a proper distinction can be made between acceptable inducements and those that constitute undue influence or coercion. No hard-and-fast criterion can be stipulated for making this distinction. However, one approach would be to consider the possible motivations for participating in research, according to the following schema. People may,for example:
All of these situations apply to some extent in research. Situation (b) is the standard presupposition in Phase II or III clinical trials. Prospective participants weigh the risks and potential benefits, recognizing that there may be some risk to themselves but also some possible benefit and that the research as a whole may provide benefits to others. Situation (c) is the standard for research not designed to provide direct benefit to participants, but, for example, to determine the safety of drugs in Phase I studies, to discover basic physiological mechanisms, or to arrive at baseline data. Situation (d) captures the idea of undue inducement when people make a rational refusal based on perceived risk, but then agree to accept the risk only when provided with a considerable material reward. Situation (e), by definition, is the paradigm of coercion: In hierarchical groups, in coercive settings, or under threat, individuals agree to participate in research because they fear the consequences of refusal. In this situation, their participation is coerced, not voluntary. Situation (e), therefore, is ethically prohibited. In principle, there is no difference between the sort of motivation that prompts people anywhere to volunteer for research—situation (b)—and what may induce people in developing countries to agree to participate. The more difficult challenge lies in situation (d): Does the prospect of receiving medical care as a benefit during (or possibly after) the research prompt people in developing countries to undertake serious risks they would other wise refuse to accept? There can be no general answer to this question, which can be determined only on a case-by-case basis. In studies with the usual range of risks, the provision of medical care may be an inducement to participate, but there is little reason to believe it is an undue inducement. Recalling the definition of undue influence cited earlier—"an excessive, unwarranted,inappropriate or improper reward"—it is reasonable to conclude that providing medical care to research participants is warranted, appropriate, and proper. One might object that this definition is embedded in a document created in the United States—a wealthy, industrialized country—and therefore is irrelevant to resource-poor countries. The reply to this objection is twofold. First, poor people exist in every country, and participation in a clinical trial often is the only way that uninsured individuals in the United States can gain access to some medical care. Yet, no one could reasonably maintain that the poor or uninsured should be excluded from participation in research or that it would be ethically acceptable to deny them medical benefits that they could not otherwise obtain. Second, the problem may not lie in the idea that an offer to possibly receive medical care is an inducement, but rather in the difficulty of determining when such an offer—admittedly an inducement—becomes undue. Those who argue that participation in research constitutes an undue inducement for poor people in developing countries would have to maintain that offering high-quality medical care and treatment that participants would not otherwise receive is unwarranted and inappropriate. However, the provision of medical care or treatment that would not otherwise be available to research participants should not, in principle, be construed as an undue influence to participate. This conclusion is supported by developing country researchers surveyed by Kass and Hyder: 64 percent stated that participants joined research projects in order to obtain benefits.33 Many researchers interviewed in focus groups for this same study seemed to believe that this was acceptable, given the overall risk/benefit ratio of the research; some focus group respondents remarked that providing significant benefits essentially left potential participants with no reasonable choice except to participate, but they did not specifically refer to this as undue inducement.34 NBAC concludes that although the potential benefits of participation in research may be an inducement for those in developing countries who lack access to medical care to participate in research, this does not sufficiently diminish the voluntariness of their decision in a way that would make their consent ethically invalid. Somewhat more problematic are clinical trials studying a new intervention in which members of a control group receive an established effective treatment that is unavailable outside the trial. Does provision of the established effective treatment constitute an undue inducement to participate? This situation can be cast in the form of a dilemma. If providing treatment otherwise unavailable to members of a control group is an undue inducement and hence ethically unacceptable, then the only ethically acceptable research design in such situations would be that of a placebo control or some other substandard treatment that is available. However, as discussed in Chapter 2, placebo-controlled trials may be ethically unacceptable in cases in which the disease is life threatening or permanently disabling and established effective treatments exist for the condition. The dilemma arises because of the tension between the potential loss of full voluntariness on the part of participants and the probability of harm befalling those in the control arm who receive the placebo instead of an established effective treatment. As in any ethical dilemma, this one requires that moral considerations be weighed in order to determine which alternative is more acceptable. An appeal to certain ethical principles offers some insight. The well-accepted principle of nonmaleficence (Beauchamp and Childress 1994; National Commission 1979) requires that harm to participants be minimized;35however, it could never be used to justify coercion of research participants, which would entirely preclude their voluntary participation. NBAC concludes that in this situation, it is more acceptable to allow the possibility of somewhat diminished voluntariness of participation than to risk harm to participants in the control arm, who are denied an established effective treatment. This is a position consistent with other guidelines, such as those of the Medical Research Council of the United Kingdom (MRC-UK 1999). Minimizing the Therapeutic Misconception One barrier to understanding the relevant, important aspects of any proposed research is what has been called the therapeutic misconception (Appelbaum et al. 1982; Churchill et al. 1998; King 1995). This term refers to the belief that the purpose of a clinical trial is to benefit the individual patient rather than to gather data for the purpose of contributing to scientific knowledge. The trust that patients have in their physicians in the clinical setting depends on an important element of the physician patient relationship—that physicians should choose the most appropriate treatment for their individual patients. To apply that same concept to the research setting is to fall prey to the therapeutic misconception, which surfaces even when participants have received complete information (ACHRE 1996). In short, the therapeutic misconception rests on confusion between the aims of research and those of individualized medical treatment.The therapeutic misconception has been documented in a wide range of developing and developed countries. For example, in a study conducted in a clinic in Brazil, all of the women who were interviewed said that they entered the study because they "thought that the contraceptive being offered would be good for them" (Hardy et al. 1998). In some parts of the world, a different kind of complication arises from the language itself. One American respondent to the study conducted by Kass and Hyder stated the following: "In many African languages, there is no word for `research' or `science.' The word used is generally the same as the word for `medicine.' There is no concept of an experiment, placebos, etc., and despite the best translation of the most simply worded consent form, many adult subjects still have no understanding of the difference between being a research subject and receiving medical treatment."36 The researcher went on to say that "[t]his should not be a reason to exclude these people from research; in fact they are often the population who will benefit most from the research and the only population in whom the studies can be done, e.g., persons at risk of naturally acquired malaria or other tropical diseases."37 It is important to distinguish the confusion that arises from the therapeutic misconception from a related consideration. In the research setting, participants often receive beneficial clinical care. In some developing countries, the type and level of clinical care provided to research participants may not be available to those individuals outside the research context. It is not a misconception to believe that participants probably will receive good clinical care during research. But it is a misconception to believe that the purpose of clinical trials is to administer treatment rather than to conduct research. Researchers should make clear to research participants, in the initial consent process and throughout the study, which activities are elements of research and which are elements of clinical care. Recommendation 3.10: Researchers working in developing countries should indicate in their research protocols how they would minimize the likelihood that potential participants will believe mistakenly that the purpose of the research is solely to administer treatment rather than to contribute to scientific knowledge (see also Recommendation 3.2). At the same time, there is some evidence that researchers can overcome many of the obstacles to participants' understanding of lengthy complicated consent forms by devoting more time and effort to the consent process. Several empirical studies of informed consent carried out in developed countries describe a fairly elaborate, multistage consent process aimed at overcoming these barriers. Studies conducted in Chile, the Netherlands, and Switzerland found that researchers could overcome these barriers with three separate preparatory sessions conducted with potential participants (Rodenhuis et al. 1984; S ánchez et al. 1998; Tomamichel et al. 1995). For example, in approving protocols, IRBs may waive documentation of informed consent through a signature or a thumbprint, provided that the researchers provide adequate justification for the waiver and ensure adherence to the substantive ethical standard of informed consent. It is NBAC's view that in such cases, the justification, while important, also must pass public scrutiny, and we would encourage a process by which these waivers were audited by a competent body. Commentators to NBAC remarked that waivers of written consent documentation should include safeguards to ensure that individual consent is obtained. The FDA requires that clinical trial data entail some form of documentation of the consent process (21 CFR 312.62(b) and 21 CFR 812.140(a)(3)(i)), which means that an alternative form of documentation is needed for those trials submitted to the FDA that do not use individual signed consent forms. At the same time, more information is needed to determine the extent and magnitude of cultural differences in the informed consent process.
Recommendation 3.11: U.S. research regulations should be amended to permit ethics review committees to waive the requirements for written and signed consent documents in accordance with local cultural norms. Ethics review committees should grant such waivers only if the research protocol specifies how the researchers and others could verify that research participants have given their voluntary informed consent. Recommendation 3.12: The National Institutes of Health, the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, and other U.S. departments and agencies should support research that addresses specifically the informed consent process in various cultural settings. In addition, those U.S. departments and agencies that conduct During the course of its deliberations, NBAC found that there is a great deal of support in developing countries for the requirement of voluntary, individual informed consent. The surveys conducted by Kass and Hyder lend considerable support to the view that both developed and developing country researchers view the requirement to obtain voluntary informed consent as a critical ethical standard. Adherence to this standard requires that researchers disclose relevant information, take steps to determine that potential participants understand what they have been told, and ensure that each individual's consent is voluntary. Nevertheless, for some customs and traditions, some of the specific procedures related to the process and documentation of informed consent as stipulated in the U.S. regulations must be modified. These procedures should be sufficiently flexible to be adapted for use in various developing countries. The requirements of written consent and the participant's signature, mark, or thumbprint on consent forms are procedures that ethics review committees should be allowed to waive when researchers provide adequate justification for such waivers. Every competent adult should be able to decide freely whether to participate in research, a position adopted in previous NBAC reports (NBAC 1998; NBAC 1999). Those who wish to cede that decision to another should be able to do so, but the initial choice is still theirs. Often, personal and local circumstances complicate this choice, and many obstacles remain to achieving an ideal process. Nevertheless, adherence to a country's customs and traditions need not compromise the ethical standard of informed consent. In some circumstances, researchers should have greater flexibility in determining how they inform participants about the research and in the methods they use to document consent. In addition, potential participants may wish to involve family members in their decision to participate, and researchers may need to obtain a community leader's permission before approaching individuals in the recruitment process. NBAC believes that these recommendations represent only the first steps toward eventually reaching a point at which every competent individual, based on adequate information, can voluntarily make his or her own decision about participating in research. Notes1 The material in this chapter benefited from reports prepared by several NBAC consultants, articles published in the literature, and two unpublished studies provided to NBAC by researchers from South America (Hardy et al. 1998; Sánchez et al. 1998). The consultants' reports are as follows: Kass, N., and A. Hyder, "Attitudes and Experiences of U.S. and Developing Country Investigators Regarding U.S. Human Subjects Regulations," Marshall, P., "The Relevance of Culture for Informed Consent in U.S.-Funded International Health Research," and Sugarman, J., B. Popkin, F. Fortney, and R. Rivera, "International Perspectives on Protecting Human Research Subjects." These background papers were prepared for NBAC and are available in Volume II of this report. 2 We acknowledge that the principle of respect for persons also permits the foregoing of voluntary informed consent in certain situations, such as research involving those who lack the capacity to give consent, research involving only minimal risk, or emergency research. These areas pose their own unique issues, which will not be addressed in this report. 3 See Kass and Hyder; Marshall; and Sugarman et al. 4 See Sugarman et al., 10. 5 From data collected by Kass, N., and L. Dawson, 1999, Preliminary Focus Group Report, 9. For Kass, N., and A. Hyder, "Attitudes and Experiences of U.S. and Developing Country Investigators Regarding U.S. Human Subjects Regulations." 6 See Marshall, 18. 7 Plowe, C., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia; Pape, J.P., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. 8 See Sugarman et al., 17. 9 See Kass and Hyder. 10 See Marshall, 34. 11 Sommer, A., Testimony before NBAC. September 16, 1999. Arlington, Virginia. Meeting transcript, 214. 12 See Kass and Hyder, 6. 13 See Marshall, 17. 14 Pape, J.P., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. 15 Ibid., 32. 16 See Marshall, 15. 17 Plowe, C., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. Meeting transcript, 151. 18 Pape, J.P., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. 19 See Kass and Hyder. 20 From data collected by Kass, N., and L. Dawson, 1999, Preliminary Focus Group Report. For Kass, N., and A. Hyder, "Attitudes and Experiences of U.S. and Developing Country Investigators Regarding U.S. Human Subjects Regulations." 21 See Kass and Hyder, 43. 22 From data collected by Kass, N., and L. Dawson, 1999, Preliminary Focus Group Report, 8. For Kass, N., and A. Hyder, "Attitudes and Experiences of U.S. and Developing Country Investigators Regarding U.S. Human Subjects Regulations." 23 See Marshall, 34. 24 Ibid., 22. 25 From data collected by Kass, N., and L. Dawson, 1999, Preliminary Focus Group Report, 1. For Kass, N., and A. Hyder, "Attitudes and Experiences of U.S. and Developing Country Investigators Regarding U.S. Human Subjects Regulations." 26 Plowe, C., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. 27 See Kass and Hyder, 43. 28 Sugarman and colleagues state that "investigators in one country repeatedly noted that patients who might be asked to enroll in a medical study would be skeptical of an investigator who did not involve the family in the decision making process." See Sugarman et al., 9. 29 See Marshall, 28. 30 The Constitution of the Republic of Uganda. Available at www.federo.com/Pages/Uganda_Constitution_1995.htm. Last accessed January 12, 2001.31 Loue, S., Testimony before NBAC. October 21, 1999. Washington, D.C. 32 Plowe, C., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. Meeting transcript, 106. 33 See Kass and Hyder, 56. 34 Ibid., 57. 35 This same principle is implicit in 45 CFR 46.111(a)(1), stating that in reviewing research, IRBs must determine that risks to subjects are minimized. 36 See Kass and Hyder, 41. 37 Ibid. 38 See Sugarman et al., 11. 39 Loue, S., Testimony before NBAC. October 21, 1999. Washington, D.C. Meeting transcript, 28 - 29, 40. 40 Pape, J.P., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. Meeting transcript, 32. 41 Malenga, G., Testimony before NBAC. February 29, 2000. Herndon, Virginia. Meeting transcript, 61. 42 See Marshall, 24. 43 Ibid., 26. Appelbaum, P.S., L.H. Roth, and C.W. Lidz. 1982. "The Therapeutic Misconception: Informed Consent in Psychiatric Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 1994. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. New York: Oxford University Press. Bernstein, N. 1999. "For Subjects in Haiti Study, Free AIDS Care Has a Price." New York Times 6 June, A-1. Churchill, L.R., M.L. Collins, N.M.P. King, S.G. Pemberton, and K.A. Wailoo. 1998. "Genetic Research as Therapy: Implications of `Gene Therapy' for Informed Consent." The Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 26(1):38—47. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS). 1993. International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects. Geneva: CIOMS. Dickert, N., and C. Grady. 1999. "What's the Price of a Research Subject? Approaches to Payment for Research Participation." New England Journal of Medicine 341(3):198—203. Faden, R.R., and T.L. Beauchamp. 1986. A History and Theory of Informed Consent. New York: Oxford University Press. Hardy, E., M.J.D. Osis, S.F. Bento, A.L. Jiménez, and C.R. Carnevalli. 1998. Informed Consent and Fertility Regulation in Brazil. Final Report. Campinas, São Paulo, Brazil. Unpublished. Ijsselmuiden, C.B., and R.R. Faden. 1992. "Research and Informed Consent in Africa—Another Look." New England Journal of Medicine 326(12):830—844. International Conference on Harmonisation of Technical Requirements for Registration of Pharmaceuticals for Human Use (ICH). 1996. ICH Harmonised Tripartite Guideline. Guideline for Good Clinical Practice. Geneva: ICH Secretariat, International Federation for Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association. King, N.M.P. 1995. "Experimental Treatment: Oxymoron or Aspiration?" Hastings Center Report 25(4):6—15. Leach, A., S. Hilton, B.M. Greenwood, E. Manneh, B. Dibba, A. Wilkins, and E.K. Mulholland. 1999. "An Evaluation of the Informed Consent Procedure Used During a Trial of a Haemophilus influenzae type b Conjugate Vaccine Undertaken in The Gambia, West Africa." Social Science and Medicine 48:139—148. Loue, S., and D. Okello. 2000. "Research Bioethics in the Ugandan Context II: Procedural and Substantive Reform." Law, Medicine, and Ethics 28(2):165—173. Love, R.R., and N.C. Fost. 1997. "Ethical and Regulatory Challenges in a Randomized Control Trial of Adjuvant Treatment for Breast Cancer in Vietnam." Journal of Investigative Medicine 45(8):423—431. Macklin, R. 1981. "`Due' and `Undue' Inducements: On Paying Money to Research Subjects." IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 3(5):1—6. ———. 1982. "Beyond Paternalism." IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 4(3):6—7. Medical Research Council of the United Kingdom (MRC-UK). 1999. Interim Guidelines for Research Involving Human Participants in Developing Societies: Ethical Guidelines for MRC-Sponsored Studies. London: MRC. National Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC). 1998. Research Involving Persons with Mental Disorders That May Affect Decisionmaking Capacity. 2 vols. Rockville, MD: U.S. Government Printing Office. ———. 1999. Research Involving Human Biological Materials: Ethical Issues and Policy Guidance. 2 vols. Rockville, MD: U.S. Government Printing Office. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (National Commission). 1979. Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research. Washington, D.C.: Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. National Consensus Conference on Bioethics and Health Research in Uganda (National Consensus Conference). 1997. Guidelines for the Conduct of Health Research Involving Human Subjects in Uganda. Kampala, Uganda: National Consensus Conference. Newton, L. 1990. "Ethical Imperialism and Informed Consent." IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 12(3):10—11. Preziosi, M.P., A. Yam, M. Ndiaye, A. Simaga, G. Simondon, and S.G.F. Wassilak. 1997. "Practical Experiences in Obtaining Informed Consent for a Vaccine Trial in Rural Africa." New England Journal of Medicine 336(5):370—373. Rodenhuis, S., W.J.A. Van den Heuvel, A.A. Annyas, H.S. Koops, D.T. Sleijfer, and N.H. Mulder. 1984. "Patient Motivation and Informed Consent in a Phase I Study of an Anticancer Agent." European Journal of Cancer and Clinical Oncology 20(4):457—462. Sánchez, S., G. Salazar, and M. Tijero. 1998. Final Report of the Project Decisions and Perspectives of Women Who Participate in Contraceptive Clinical Trials. Instituto Chileno de Medicina Reproductiva. Santiago, Chile. Unpublished. Tomamichel, M., C. Sessa, S. Herzig, J. de Jong, O. Pagani, Y. Willems, and F. Cavalli. 1995. "Informed Consent for Phase I Studies: Evaluation of Quantity and Quality of Information Provided to Patients." Annals of Oncology 6(4):363—369. United Nations, General Assembly. 1996. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. Res 2200A(XXI) at 52, UN Doc A/6316, 999 U.N.T.S. 171. New York: United Nations. World Medical Association (WMA). Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects (adopted 18th WMA General Assembly, Helsinki, Finland, June 1964; amended: 29th WMA General Assembly, Tokyo, Japan, October 1975; 35th WMA General Assembly, Venice, Italy, October 1983; 41st WMA General Assembly, Hong Kong, September 1989; 48th WMA General Assembly, Somerset West, Republic of South Africa, October 1996; and 52nd WMA General Assembly, Edinburgh, Scotland, October 2000). Ferney-Voltaire, France: WMA. Available at www.wma.net/e/policy/17-c_e.html.Last accessed January 12, 2001.
|